This reminds me of a similar phenomenon. I am wondering how you see recent EU threats to suspend funds from Member States, based on a concept called “the rule of law.”
There are phrases—“the rule of law,” “human dignity,” “democratic values”—that are much bandied about these days. Whenever I hear them, I feel the intellectual ground crumbling beneath my feet. I am never exactly sure what is intended.
In general, the European Union, like any organization, can make adoption of certain substantive principles a precondition of inclusion. For example, if the EU wants central tenets of its organization to include a commitment to transgender rights and the abolition of the death penalty, so be it.
What is questionable is when substantive disagreements are camouflaged in moralizing platitudes,
as I pointed out in earlier article with regards to immigration law and policies.
To return to the death penalty, there are credible arguments that can be made for abolition. Nonetheless, the claim that the principle of “human dignity” requires this position is unpersuasive. If there is a modern philosopher most associated with the concept of human dignity, it is Immanuel Kant. He, of course, was a proponent of capital punishment.
In your opinion, what explains the deep Western devotion to the abolition of the death penalty? What does it suggest about the Western society?
The first point to make, which is implicit in your question, is that the devotion to abolition seems peculiarly Western. Political leaders and public intellectuals in the Western world often cast the movement towards abolition as a global phenomenon, but as I pointed out in an article a few years ago, this is inaccurate. The United States is not alone in using capital punishment. China, Japan, India, and much of the Islamic world retain the death penalty.
As to what explains
the Western devotion to the abolition of the death penalty, there are two ways of looking at it.
One interpretation, preferred by leading intellectuals, such as the prolific American author, Steven Pinker, is that Western ideals, as incorporated for example in the European Convention on Human Rights, reflect the pinnacle of civilization. The rest of the world is ascending, as it were, to the recognition of human dignity and rejection of state-authorized violence that is encapsulated in the formal abolition of capital punishment.
In this interpretation, the entire world is progressing towards the moral truths already accepted by the West.
In Pinker’s words: “Capital Punishment is on death row – if trends continue, it should be gone from the world by 2026.
”There is a less generous interpretation of the abolitionist trend in the Western world. Perhaps the retention of the death penalty is a barometer of civilizational confidence. To shrink from imposing full justice on the worst of criminals reflects a lack of moral confidence. In this view, death penalty abolition is the terminal point of a deep epistemological skepticism.
Distinctions that were once taken for granted—citizen versus stranger; male versus female; criminals versus the law-abiding—do not come easily, if they come at all, to many in the West.
One might recall an observation of Friedrich Nietzsche: “There is a point in the history of society when it becomes so pathologically soft and tender that among other things it sides even with those who harm it, criminals, and does this quite seriously and honestly.”
So, summing up, the abolition of the death penalty can be construed either as a moral ascent or a civilizational decline. I leave it to your readers to judge which of these interpretations is more persuasive.